Senin, 04 Agustus 2014

[P227.Ebook] Download But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

Download But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

Thus, this site provides for you to cover your trouble. We show you some referred books But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman in all types and themes. From usual writer to the renowned one, they are all covered to supply in this website. This But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman is you're searched for publication; you merely should visit the link web page to receive this internet site and then go for downloading. It will certainly not take sometimes to obtain one book But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman It will certainly depend upon your web connection. Just acquisition and also download the soft documents of this publication But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman



But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

Download But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman. Change your routine to put up or lose the time to only chat with your close friends. It is done by your everyday, don't you feel tired? Currently, we will certainly reveal you the new habit that, actually it's a very old behavior to do that could make your life more qualified. When really feeling tired of always talking with your good friends all spare time, you could locate the book entitle But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman and after that review it.

As we stated previously, the modern technology aids us to always recognize that life will certainly be constantly much easier. Reviewing publication But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman routine is additionally among the perks to obtain today. Why? Innovation could be used to provide the book But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman in only soft documents system that could be opened every single time you desire and all over you require without bringing this But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman prints in your hand.

Those are several of the perks to take when getting this But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman by on-line. But, exactly how is the way to obtain the soft documents? It's extremely appropriate for you to see this web page since you can obtain the link page to download the book But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman Merely click the web link supplied in this short article and goes downloading. It will certainly not take significantly time to get this e-book But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman, like when you need to opt for book shop.

This is additionally among the reasons by obtaining the soft file of this But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman by online. You may not require even more times to spend to see the publication store and also look for them. Occasionally, you likewise do not discover guide But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman that you are searching for. It will waste the moment. However here, when you see this page, it will certainly be so very easy to obtain as well as download and install guide But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman It will not take sometimes as we specify in the past. You can do it while doing something else in the house or perhaps in your workplace. So simple! So, are you question? Simply practice what we provide right here as well as review But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About The Present As If It Were The Past, By Chuck Klosterman exactly what you love to read!

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman

New York Times bestselling author Chuck Klosterman asks questions that are profound in their simplicity: How certain are we about our understanding of gravity? How certain are we about our understanding of time? What will be the defining memory of rock music, five hundred years from today? How seriously should we view the content of our dreams? How seriously should we view the content of television? Are all sports destined for extinction? Is it possible that the greatest artist of our era is currently unknown (or—weirder still—widely known, but entirely disrespected)? Is it possible that we “overrate” democracy? And perhaps most disturbing, is it possible that we’ve reached the end of knowledge?

Klosterman visualizes the contemporary world as it will appear to those who'll perceive it as the distant past.�Kinetically slingshotting through a broad spectrum of objective and subjective problems, But What If We’re Wrong? is built on interviews with a variety of creative thinkers—George Saunders, David Byrne, Jonathan Lethem, Kathryn Schulz, Neil deGrasse Tyson, Brian Greene, Junot D�az, Amanda Petrusich, Ryan Adams, Nick Bostrom, Dan Carlin, and Richard Linklater, among others—interwoven with the type of high-wire humor and nontraditional analysis only Klosterman would dare to attempt. It’s a seemingly impossible achievement: a book about the things we cannot know, explained as if we did. It’s about how we live now, once “now” has become “then.”

  • Sales Rank: #3547 in Books
  • Published on: 2016-06-07
  • Released on: 2016-06-07
  • Original language: English
  • Number of items: 1
  • Dimensions: 8.60" h x 1.00" w x 5.67" l, 1.25 pounds
  • Binding: Hardcover
  • 288 pages

Review
“Full of intelligence and insights, as the author gleefully turns ideas upside down to better understand them.... This book will become a popular book club selection because it makes readers think. Replete with lots of nifty, whimsical footnotes, this clever, speculative book challenges our beliefs with jocularity and perspicacity.”�—Kirkus�(starred review)

“Klosterman�conducts a series of intriguing thought experiments in this delightful new book...Klosterman’s trademark humor and unique curiosity propel the reader through the book. He remains one of the most insightful critics of pop culture writing today and this is his most thought-provoking and memorable book yet.”�—Publishers Weekly�(starred review)

“A spin class for the brain… Klosterman challenges readers to reexamine the stability of basic concepts, and in doing so broadens our perspectives…. An engaging and entertaining workout for the mind led by one of today’s funniest and most thought-provoking writers.”�—Library Journal�(starred review)

“Klosterman is outlining the ideology of a contrarian here and reminding us of the important role that revisionism plays in cultural writing. What matters is the way he thinks about thinking—and the way he makes you think about how you think. And, in the end, this is all that criticism can really hope to do.”�—Sonny Bunch,�The Washington Post

“[Klosterman’s] most wide-ranging accomplishment to date… As inquisitive, thoughtful and dryly funny as ever, But What If We’re Wrong?... [is] crackling with the writer’s signature wit.”�—Will Ashton,�Pittsburgh Post-Gazette

“In But What If We’re Wrong? [Klosterman] takes on the really big picture . . . He ranges far and wide over the realm of known knowns and known unknowns.”�—Brigitte Frase,�Minneapolis Star Tribune

“I have often wondered how the times I live in will be remembered once they turn into History. It never occurred to me to figure out how to write a book about it, though, which is one of the reasons why Chuck Klosterman is smarter than I am.”�—Aimee Levitt,�The Chicago Reader

“Klosterman has proven himself an insightful and evolving philosopher for popular consumption . . . In his latest, But What If We’re Wrong?, Klosterman probes the very notions of existence and longevity, resulting perhaps in the most mind-expanding writing of his career.”�—Max Kyburz,�Gothamist

“Chuck Klosterman is no time traveler, but he's got a lot of ideas about how the future will shake out . . . in [But What If We’re Wrong?] he ponders the limits of humanity’s search for truth.”�—Chris Weller,�Tech Insider

“Prolific pop-culture critic Chuck Klosterman tackles his most ambitious project yet in new book�But What If We’re Wrong?, which combines research, personal reflections and interviews.”�—Alexandra Cavallo,�The Improper Bostonian

“This book is brilliant and addictively readable. It's also mandatory reading for anyone who loves history and for anyone who claims to have a capacity for forecasting. It'll probably make them angry because it turns so many sacred assumptions upside down—but that's what the future does. Klosterman's writing style is direct, highly personal and robotically crisp—he's like a stranger on the seat next to you on a plane who gives you a billion dollar idea. A terrific book.”�—Douglas Coupland

About the Author
Chuck Klosterman is the bestselling author of seven books of nonfiction (including�Sex, Drugs, and Cocoa Puffs and I Wear the Black Hat) and two novels (Downtown Owl and The Visible Man). He has written for The New York Times, The Washington Post, GQ, Esquire, Spin, The Guardian, The Believer, Billboard, The A.V. Club, and ESPN. Klosterman served as the Ethicist for The New York Times Magazine for three years, appeared as himself in the LCD Soundsystem documentary Shut Up and Play the Hits, and was an original founder of the website Grantland with Bill Simmons.

Excerpt. � Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.
***This excerpt is from an advance uncorrected proof***

Copyright �2016 Chuck Klosterman

I’ve spent most of my life being wrong.

Not about everything. Just about most things.

I mean, sometimes I get stuff right. I married the right person. I’ve never purchased life insurance as an investment. The first time undrafted free agent Tony Romo led a touchdown drive against the Giants on�Monday Night Football, I told my roommate, “I think this guy will have a decent career.” At a New Year’s Eve party in 2008, I predicted Michael Jackson would unexpectedly die within the next twelve months, an anecdote I shall casually recount at every New Year’s party I’ll ever attend for the rest of my life. But these are the exceptions. It is far, far easier for me to catalog the various things I’ve been wrong about: My insistence that I would never own a cell phone. The time I wagered $100—against $1—that Barack Obama would never become president (or even receive the Democratic nomination). My three‑week obsession over the looming Y2K crisis, prompting me to hide bundles of cash, bottled water, and Oreo cookies throughout my one‑ bedroom apartment. At this point, my wrongness doesn’t even surprise me. I almost anticipate it. Whenever people tell me I’m wrong about something, I might disagree with them in conversation, but—in my mind—I assume their accusation is justified, even when I’m relatively certain they’re wrong, too.

Yet these failures are small potatoes.

These micro‑moments of wrongness are personal: I assumed the answer to something was “A,” but the true answer was “B” or “C” or “D.” Reasonable parties can disagree on the unknowable, and the passage of time slowly proves one party to be slightly more reasonable than the other. The stakes are low. If I’m wrong about something specific, it’s (usually) my own fault, and someone else is (usually, but not totally) right.

But what about the things we’re�all�wrong about?

What about ideas that are so accepted and internalized that we’re not even in a position to question their fallibility? These are ideas so ingrained in the collective consciousness that it seems fool‑ hardy to even wonder if they’re potentially untrue. Sometimes these seem like questions only a child would ask, since children aren’t paralyzed by the pressures of consensus and common sense. It’s a dissonance that creates the most unavoidable of intellectual paradoxes: When you ask smart people if they believe there are major ideas currently accepted by the culture at large that will eventually be proven false, they will say, “Well, of course. There must be. That phenomenon has been experienced by every generation who’s ever lived, since the dawn of human history.” Yet offer those same people a laundry list of contemporary ideas that might fit that description, and they’ll be tempted to reject them all.

It is impossible to examine questions we refuse to ask. These are the big potatoes.

Like most people, I like to think of myself as a skeptical person. But I’m pretty much in the tank for gravity. It’s the natural force most recognized as perfunctorily central to everything we under‑ stand about everything else. If an otherwise well‑executed argument contradicts the principles of gravity, the argument is inevitably altered to make sure that it does not. The fact that I’m not a physicist makes my adherence to gravity especially unyielding, since I don’t know anything about gravity that wasn’t told to me by someone else. My confidence in gravity is absolute, and I believe this will be true until the day I die (and if someone subsequently throws my dead body out of a window, I believe my corpse’s rate of acceleration will be 9.8 m/s2).

And I’m probably wrong.

Maybe not completely, but partially. And maybe not today, but eventually.

“There is a very, very good chance that our understanding of gravity will not be the same in five hundred years. In fact, that’s the one arena where I would think that most of our contemporary evidence is circumstantial, and that the way we think about gravity will be very different.” These are the words of Brian Greene, a theoretical physicist at Columbia University who writes books with titles like�Icarus at the Edge of Time. He’s the kind of physicist famous enough to guest star on a CBS sitcom, assuming that sit‑ com is�The Big Bang Theory. “For two hundred years, Isaac Newton had gravity down. There was almost no change in our thinking until 1907. And then from 1907 to 1915, Einstein radically changes our understanding of gravity: No longer is gravity just a force, but a warping of space and time. And now we realize quantum mechanics must have an impact on how we describe gravity within very short distances. So there’s all this work that really starts to pick up in the 1980s, with all these new ideas about how gravity would work in the microscopic realm. And then string theory comes along, trying to understand how gravity behaves on a small scale, and that gives us a description—which we don’t know to be right or wrong—that equates to a quantum theory of gravity. Now, that requires extra dimensions of space. So the understanding of gravity starts to have radical implications for our understanding of reality. And now there are folks, inspired by these findings, who are trying to rethink gravity itself. They suspect gravity might not even be a fundamental force, but an emergent1 force. So I do think—and I think many would agree—that gravity is the least stable of our ideas, and the most ripe for a major shift.”

If that sounds confusing, don’t worry—I was confused when Greene explained it to me as I sat in his office

1 This means that gravity might just be a manifestation of other forces—not a force itself, but the peripheral result of something else. Greene’s analogy was with the idea of temperature: Our skin can sense warmth on a hot day, but “warmth” is not some independent thing that exists on its own. Warmth is just the consequence of invisible atoms moving around very fast, creating the�sensation�of temperature. We feel it, but it’s not really there. So if gravity were an emergent force, it would mean that gravity isn’t the central power pulling things to the Earth, but the tangential consequence of something else we can’t yet explain. We feel it, but it’s not there. It would almost make the whole idea of “gravity” a semantic construction.

(and he explained it to me twice). There are essential components to physics and math that I will never understand in any functional way, no matter what I read or how much time I invest. A post‑gravity world is beyond my comprehension. But the concept of a post‑gravity world helps me think about something else: It helps me understand the pre‑ gravity era. And I don’t mean the days before Newton published�Principia�in 1687, or even that period from the late 1500s when Galileo was (allegedly) dropping balls off the Leaning Tower of Pisa and inadvertently inspiring the Indigo Girls. By the time those events occurred, the notion of gravity was already drifting through the scientific ether. Nobody had pinned it down, but the mathematical intelligentsia knew Earth was rotating around the sun in an elliptical orbit (and that�something�was making this hap‑ pen). That was around three hundred years ago. I’m more fixated on how life was another three hundred years before that. Here was a period when the best understanding of why objects did not spontaneously f loat was some version of what Aristotle had argued more than a thousand years prior: He believed all objects craved their “natural place,” and that this place was the geocentric center of the universe, and that the geocentric center of the universe was Earth. In other words, Aristotle believed that a dropped rock fell to the earth because rocks belonged on earth and wanted to be there.

So let’s consider the magnitude of this shift: Aristotle—arguably the greatest philosopher who ever lived—writes the book�Physics�and defines his argument. His view exists unchallenged for almost two thousand years. Newton (history’s most meaningful mathematician, even to this day) eventually watches an apocryphal apple fall from an apocryphal tree and inverts the entire human under‑ standing of why the world works as it does. Had this been explained to those people in the fourteenth century with no understanding of science—in other words, pretty much everyone else alive in the fourteenth century—Newton’s explanation would have seemed way, way crazier than what they currently believed: Instead of claiming that Earth’s existence defined reality and that there was something essentialist about why rocks acted like rocks, Newton was advocating an invisible, imperceptible force field that some‑ how anchored the moon in place.

We now know (“know”) that Newton’s concept was correct. Humankind had been collectively,�objectively�wrong for roughly twenty centuries. Which provokes three semi‑related questions:


���•�If mankind could believe something false was objectively true for two thousand years, why do we ref lexively assume that our current understanding of gravity—which we’ve embraced for a mere three hundred fifty years—will some‑ how exist forever?
���•�Is it possible that this type of problem has simply been solved? What if Newton’s answer really is—more or less— thefinalanswer, and the only one we will ever need? Because if that is true, it would mean we’re at the end of a process that has defined the experience of being alive. It would mean certain intellectual quests would no longer be necessary.
���•�Which statement is more reasonable to make: “I believe grav‑ ity exists” or “I’m 99.9 percent certain that gravity exists”? Certainly, the second statement issafer. But if we’re going to acknowledge even the slightest possibility of being wrong about gravity, we’re pretty much giving up on the possibility of being right about anything at all.

There’s a popular website that sells books (and if you purchased this particular book, consumer research suggests there’s a 41 per‑ cent chance you ordered it from this particular site). Book sales constitute only about 7 percent of this website’s total sales, but books are the principal commodity this enterprise is known for. Part of what makes the site successful is its user‑generated con‑ tent; consumers are given the opportunity to write reviews of their various purchases, even if they never actually consumed the book they’re critiquing. Which is amazing, particularly if you want to read negative, one‑star reviews of Herman Melville’s�Moby-Dick.

“Pompous, overbearing, self‑indulgent, and insufferable. This is the worst book I’ve ever read,” wrote one dissatisfied customer in 2014. “Weak narrative, poor structure, incomplete plot threads, � of the chapters are extraneous, and the author often confuses himself with the protagonist. One chapter is devoted to the fact that whales don’t have noses. Another is on the color white.” Interestingly, the only other purchase this person elected to review was a Hewlett‑Packard printer that can also send faxes, which he awarded two stars.

I can’t dispute this person’s distaste for�Moby-Dick. I’m sure he did hate reading it. But his choice to state this opinion in public— almost entirely devoid of critical context, unless you count his take on the HP printer—is more meaningful than the opinion itself. Publicly attacking�Moby-Dick�is shorthand for arguing that what we’re socialized to believe about art is fundamentally questionable. Taste is subjective, but some subjective opinions are casually expressed the same way we articulate principles of math or science. There isn’t an ongoing cultural debate over the merits of�Moby- Dick: It’s not merely an epic novel, but a transformative literary innovation that helps define how novels are supposed to be viewed. Any discussion about the clich�d concept of “the Great American Novel” begins with this book. The work itself is not above criticism, but no individual criticism has any impact; at this point, attacking�Moby-Dick�only reflects the contrarianism of the critic. We all start from the supposition that�Moby-Dick is accepted as self‑evidently awesome, including (and perhaps especially) those who disagree with that assertion.

So how did this happen?

Melville publishes�Moby-Dick�in 1851, basing his narrative on the real‑life 1839 account of a murderous sperm whale nicknamed “Mocha Dick.” The initial British edition is around nine hundred pages. Melville, a moderately successful author at the time of the novel’s release, assumes this book will immediately be seen as a masterwork. This is his premeditated intention throughout the writing process. But the reviews are mixed, and some are contemptuous (“it repels the reader” is the key takeaway from one of the very first reviews in the London�Spectator). It sells poorly—at the time of Melville’s death, total sales hover below five thousand copies. The failure ruins Melville’s life: He becomes an alcoholic and a poet, and eventually a customs inspector. When he dies destitute in 1891, one has to assume his perspective on�Moby-Dick�is some‑ thing along the lines of “Well, I guess that didn’t work. Maybe I should have spent fewer pages explaining how to tie complicated knots.” For the next thirty years, nothing about the reception of this book changes. But then World War I happens, and—somehow, and for reasons that can’t be totally explained2—modernists living in postwar America start to view literature through a different lens. There is a Melville revival. The concept of what a novel is supposed to accomplish shifts in his direction and amplifies with each passing generation, eventually prompting people (like the 2005 director of Columbia University’s American studies pro‑ gram) to classify�Moby-Dick�as “the most ambitious book ever conceived by an American writer.” Pundits and cranks can disagree with that assertion, but no one cares if they do. Melville’s place in history is secure, almost as if he were an explorer or an inventor: When the prehistoric remains of a previously unknown predatory whale were discovered in Peru in 2010, the massive creature was eventually named�Livyatan melvillei. A century after his death, Melville gets his own extinct super‑whale named after him, in tribute to a book that commercially tanked. That’s an interesting kind of career.

Now, there’s certainly a difference between collective, objective wrongness (e.g., misunderstanding gravity for twenty centuries) and collective, subjective wrongness (e.g., not caring about�Moby- Dick�for seventy‑five years). The machinations of the transitionsare completely different. Yet both scenarios hint at a practical reality and a modern problem. The practical reality is that any present‑tense version of the world is unstable. What we currently consider to be true—both objectively and subjectively—is habitually provisional. But the modern problem is that reevaluating what we consider “true” is becoming increasingly difficult. Superficially, it’s become easier for any one person to dispute the status quo: Everyone has a viable platform to criticize�Moby-Dick�(or, I suppose, a mediocre HP printer). If there’s a rogue physicist in Winnipeg who doesn’t believe in gravity, he can self‑publish a book that outlines his argument and potentially attract a larger audience than�Principia�found during its first hundred years of existence. But increasing the capacity for the reconsideration of ideas is not the same as actually changing those ideas (or even�allowing�them to change by their own momentum).

We live in an age where virtually no content is lost and virtually all content is shared. The sheer amount of information about every current idea makes those concepts difficult to contradict, particularly in a framework where public consensus has become the ultimate arbiter of validity. In other words, we’re starting to behave as if we’ve reached the end of human knowledge. And while that notion is undoubtedly false, the sensation of certitude it generates is paralyzing.

In her book�Being Wrong, author Kathryn Schulz spends a few key pages on the concept of “na�ve realism.” Schulz notes that while there are few conscious proponents of na�ve realism, “that doesn’t mean there are no na�ve realists.” I would go a step further than Schulz; I suspect most conventionally intelligent people are na�ve realists, and I think it might be the defining intellectual quality of this era. The straightforward definition of na�ve realism doesn’t seem that outlandish: It’s a theory that suggests the world is exactly as it appears. Obviously, this viewpoint creates a lot of opportunity for colossal wrongness (e.g., “The sun appears to move across the sky, so the sun must be orbiting Earth”). But my personal characterization of na�ve realism is wider and more insidious. I think it operates as the manifestation of two ingrained beliefs:


���•�“When considering any question, I must be rational and logical, to the point of dismissing any unverifiable data as preposterous,” and
���•�“When considering any question, I’m going to assume that the information we currently have is all the information that will ever be available.”

Here’s an extreme example: the possibility of life after death. When considered rationally, there is no justification for believing that anything happens to anyone upon the moment of his or her death. There is no reasonable counter to the prospect of nothing‑ ness. Any anecdotal story about “floating toward a white light” or Shirley MacLaine’s past life on Atlantis or the details in�Heaven Is for Real�are automatically (and justifiably) dismissed by any secular intellectual. Yet this wholly logical position discounts the over‑ whelming likelihood that we currently don’t know something critical about the experience of life, much less the ultimate conclusion to that experience. There are so many things we don’t know about energy, or the way energy is transferred, or why energy (which can’t be created or destroyed) exists at all. We can’t truly conceive the conditions of a multidimensional reality, even though we’re (probably) already living inside one. We have a limited under‑ standing of consciousness. We have a limited understanding of time, and of the

perception of time, and of the possibility that all time is happening at once. So while it seems unrealistic to seriously

2 The qualities that spurred this rediscovery can, arguably, be quantified: The isolation and brotherhood the sailors experience mirrors the experience of fight‑ ing in a war, and the battle against a faceless evil whale could be seen as a metaphor for the battle against the faceless abstraction of evil Germany. But the fact that these details can be quantified is still not a satisfactory explanation as to why�Moby-Dick�became the specific novel that was selected and elevated. It’s not like�Moby-Dick�is the only book that could have served this role.

consider the prospect of life after death, it seems equally na�ve to assume that our contemporary understanding of this phenomenon is remotely complete. We have no idea what we don’t know, or what we’ll eventually learn, or what might be true despite our perpetual inability to comprehend what that truth is.

It’s impossible to understand the world of today until today has become tomorrow.

This is no brilliant insight, and only a fool would disagree. But it’s remarkable how habitually this truth is ignored. We constantly pretend our perception of the present day will not seem ludicrous in retrospect, simply because there doesn’t appear to be any other option. Yet there�is�another option, and the option is this: We must start from the premise that—in all likelihood—we are already wrong. And not “wrong” in the sense that we are examining questions and coming to incorrect conclusions, because most of our conclusions are reasoned and coherent. The problem is with the questions themselves.

Most helpful customer reviews

7 of 7 people found the following review helpful.
I read a lot of the reviews and they seem split between disappointment that the Klosterman of old
By Aladeen
I always look forward to a new Chuck Klosterman book, and this one delivered the goods, but not in a way that I was expecting. I read a lot of the reviews and they seem split between disappointment that the Klosterman of old, the insatiably curious pop culturist, has moved on to bigger and more abstract topics. In my opinion, we've seen that he can deconstruct "The Real World"...I am personally glad that he's trying to figure out reality, whether or not we can trust recorded history, the essence of time, etc. He is really hunting big game, here. The reader has to pay close attention so there's some work involved. It reminds me of when someone very smart is explaining something quite complicated and the explanation requires you to hang in with them so that you don't lose the train of thought. If your mind wanders of onto tangents, you're going to lose it, and even then you still might not be able to explain it later to your friends, but it was exciting just to follow the thought process as it unfolded. I hope he keeps doing this kind of stuff.

6 of 6 people found the following review helpful.
Interesting premise; weak development
By steve c.
There is little to take away from the author's bold undertaking. Each chapter sets out big questions, but provides little substance. Author seems more concerned with amusing and contradicting himself, as opposed to developing logical and thoughts provoking theories. Disappointing.

1 of 1 people found the following review helpful.
Rough around the edges but more than worthwhile
By Anjan Patnaik
Klosterman is engaging in an interesting thought exercise. He's trying to problematics certainty by making arguments about how uncertain things can be. And while he often meanders and sometimes posits questionable premises of his own to further his argument, he's ingeniously protected by the underlying assumption of his project: that what seems to be wrong might be worth looking at (this of
Course has its own set of logical circles to run). But if you view his book more as a reflection on our collective cultural evaluation of academia, athletics , arts and everything else you get a truly interesting and entertaining ideation of how we've done things and how we might continue to do them.

Klosterman has written a book that at the very least points the so called epl-jersey wearing Donnie Dario attending hipsters a direction for becoming cultural experts and at best provides some insight into how we process genius and change (rationally and not)

See all 140 customer reviews...

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman PDF
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman EPub
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman Doc
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman iBooks
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman rtf
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman Mobipocket
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman Kindle

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman PDF

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman PDF

But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman PDF
But What If We're Wrong?: Thinking About the Present As If It Were the Past, by Chuck Klosterman PDF

Tidak ada komentar:

Posting Komentar